I’d like to introduce and discuss the otherworldly cardinals, a large cardinal notion that frequently arises in set-theoretic analysis, but which until now doesn’t seem yet to have been given its own special name. So let us do so here.
I was put on to the topic by Jason Chen, a PhD student at UC Irvine working with Toby Meadows, who brought up the topic recently on Twitter:
Do these cardinals have special names: α's such that there is some β with V_α being an elementary substructure of V_β (so they form a proper subset of worldly cardinals); and a stratified version: α's such that there is some β, with V_α being a Σ_n-elementary substructure of V_β.
In response, I had suggested the otherworldly terminology, a play on the fact that the two cardinals will both be worldly, and so we have in essence two closely related worlds, looking alike. We discussed the best way to implement the terminology and its extensions. The main idea is the following:
Main Definition. An ordinal is otherworldly if for some ordinal . In this case, we say that is otherworldly to.
It is an interesting exercise to see that every otherworldly cardinal is in fact also worldly, which means , and from this it follows that is a strong limit cardinal and indeed a -fixed point and even a -hyperfixed point and more.
Theorem. Every otherworldly cardinal is also worldly.
Proof. Suppose that is otherworldly, so that for some ordinal . It follows that must in fact be a cardinal, since otherwise it would be the order type of a relation on a set in , which would be isomorphic to an ordinal in but not in . And since is not otherworldly, we see that must be an uncountable cardinal. Since is transitive, we get now easily that satisfies extensionality, regularity, union, pairing, power set, separation and infinity. The only axiom remaining is replacement. If obeys a functional relation in for all , where , then agrees with that, and also sees that the range is contained in , which is a set in . So agrees that the range is a set. So fulfills the replacement axiom.
Corollary. A cardinal is otherworldly if and only if it is fully correct in a worldly cardinal.
Proof. Once you know that otherworldly cardinals are worldly, this amounts to a restatement of the definition. If , then is worldly, and is correct in .
Let me prove next that whenever you have an otherworldly cardinal, then you will also have a lot of worldly cardinals, not just these two.
Theorem. Every otherworldly cardinal is a limit of worldly cardinals. What is more, every otherworldly cardinal is a limit of worldly cardinals having exactly the same first-order theory as , and indeed, the same -order theory for any particular .
Proof. If , then can see that is worldly and has the theory that it does. So thinks, about , that there is a cardinal whose rank initial segment has theory . Thus, also thinks this. And we can find arbitrarily large up to such that has this same theory. This argument works whether one uses the first-order theory, or the second-order theory or indeed the -order theory for any .
Theorem. If is otherworldly, then for every ordinal and natural number , there is a cardinal with and the -order theory of is the same as .
Proof. One can do the same as above, since can see that has the -order theory that it does, while also agreeing on truth with , so will agree that there should be such a cardinal .
Definition. We say that a cardinal is totally otherworldly, if it is otherworldly to arbitrarily large ordinals. It is otherworldly beyond , if it is otherworldly to some ordinal larger than . It is otherworldly up to , if it is otherworldly to ordinals cofinal in .
Theorem. Every inaccessible cardinal is a limit of otherworldly cardinals that are each otherworldly up to and to .
Proof. If is inaccessible, then a simple Löwenheim-Skolem construction shows that is the union of a continuous elementary chain Each of the cardinals arising on this chain is otherworldly up to and to .
Theorem. Every totally otherworldly cardinal is correct, meaning . Consequently, every totally otherworldly cardinal is larger than the least measurable cardinal, if it exists, and larger than the least superstrong cardinal, if it exists, and larger than the least huge cardinal, if it exists.
Proof. Every assertion is locally verifiable in the hierarchy, in that it is equivalent to an assertion of the form (for more information, see my post about Local properties in set theory). Thus, every true assertion is revealed inside any sufficiently large , and so if for arbitrarily large , then will agree on those truths.
I was a little confused at first about how two totally otherwordly cardinals interact, but now everything is clear with this next result. (Thanks to Hanul Jeon for his helpful comment below.)
Theorem. If are both totally otherworldly, then is otherworldly up to , and hence totally otherworldly in .
Proof. Since is totally otherworldly, it is correct. Since for every the cardinal is otherworldly beyond , meaning for some , then since this is a feature of , it must already be true inside . So such a can be found below , and so is otherworldly up to .
Theorem. If is totally otherworldly, then is a limit of otherworldly cardinals, and indeed, a limit of otherworldly cardinals having the same theory as .
Proof. Assume is totally otherworldly, let be the theory of , and consider any . Since there is an otherworldly cardinal above with theory , namely , and because this is a fact about and , it follows that there must be such a cardinal above inside . So is a limit of otherworldly cardinals with the same theory as .
The results above show that the consistency strength of the hypotheses are ordered as follows, with strict increases in consistency strength as you go up (assuming consistency):
ZFC + there is an inaccessible cardinal
ZFC + there is a proper class of totally otherworldly cardinals
ZFC + there is a totally otherworldly cardinal
ZFC + there is a proper class of otherworldly cardinals
ZFC + there is an otherworldly cardinal
ZFC + there is a proper class of worldly cardinals
ZFC + there is a worldly cardinal
ZFC + there is a transitive model of ZFC
ZFC + Con(ZFC)
ZFC
We might consider the natural strengthenings of otherworldliness, where one wants where is itself otherworldly. That is, is the beginning of an elementary chain of three models, not just two. This is different from having merely that and for some , because perhaps is not elementary in , even though is. Extending successively is a more demanding requirement.
One then naturally wants longer and longer chains, and ultimately we find ourselves considering various notions of rank in the rank elementary forest, which is the relation . The otherworldly cardinals are simply the non-maximal nodes in this order, while it will be interesting to consider the nodes that can be extended to longer elementary chains.