The otherwordly cardinals

I’d like to introduce and discuss the otherworldly cardinals, a large cardinal notion that frequently arises in set-theoretic analysis, but which until now doesn’t seem yet to have been given its own special name. So let us do so here.

I was put on to the topic by Jason Chen, a PhD student at UC Irvine working with Toby Meadows, who brought up the topic recently on Twitter:

In response, I had suggested the otherworldly terminology, a play on the fact that the two cardinals will both be worldly, and so we have in essence two closely related worlds, looking alike. We discussed the best way to implement the terminology and its extensions. The main idea is the following:

Main Definition. An ordinal 𝜅 is otherworldly if 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 for some ordinal 𝜆 >𝜅. In this case, we say that 𝜅 is otherworldly to 𝜆.

It is an interesting exercise to see that every otherworldly cardinal 𝜅 is in fact also worldly, which means 𝑉𝜅 ZFC, and from this it follows that 𝜅 is a strong limit cardinal and indeed a -fixed point and even a -hyperfixed point and more.

Theorem. Every otherworldly cardinal is also worldly.

Proof. Suppose that 𝜅 is otherworldly, so that 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 for some ordinal 𝜆 >𝜅. It follows that 𝜅 must in fact be a cardinal, since otherwise it would be the order type of a relation on a set in 𝑉𝜅, which would be isomorphic to an ordinal in 𝑉𝜆 but not in 𝑉𝜅. And since 𝜔 is not otherworldly, we see that 𝜅 must be an uncountable cardinal. Since 𝑉𝜅 is transitive, we get now easily that 𝑉𝜅 satisfies extensionality, regularity, union, pairing, power set, separation and infinity. The only axiom remaining is replacement. If 𝜑(𝑎,𝑏) obeys a functional relation in 𝑉𝜅 for all 𝑎 𝐴, where 𝐴 𝑉𝜅, then 𝑉𝜆 agrees with that, and also sees that the range is contained in 𝑉𝜅, which is a set in 𝑉𝜆. So 𝑉𝜅 agrees that the range is a set. So 𝑉𝜅 fulfills the replacement axiom.

Corollary. A cardinal is otherworldly if and only if it is fully correct in a worldly cardinal.

Proof. Once you know that otherworldly cardinals are worldly, this amounts to a restatement of the definition. If 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆, then 𝜆 is worldly, and 𝑉𝜅 is correct in 𝑉𝜆.

Let me prove next that whenever you have an otherworldly cardinal, then you will also have a lot of worldly cardinals, not just these two.

Theorem. Every otherworldly cardinal 𝜅 is a limit of worldly cardinals. What is more, every otherworldly cardinal is a limit of worldly cardinals having exactly the same first-order theory as 𝑉𝜅, and indeed, the same 𝛼-order theory for any particular 𝛼 <𝜅.

Proof. If 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆, then 𝑉𝜆 can see that 𝜅 is worldly and has the theory 𝑇 that it does. So 𝑉𝜆 thinks, about 𝑇, that there is a cardinal whose rank initial segment has theory 𝑇. Thus, 𝑉𝜅 also thinks this. And we can find arbitrarily large 𝛿 up to 𝜅 such that 𝑉𝛿 has this same theory. This argument works whether one uses the first-order theory, or the second-order theory or indeed the 𝛼-order theory for any 𝛼 <𝜅.

Theorem. If 𝜅 is otherworldly, then for every ordinal 𝛼 <𝜅 and natural number 𝑛, there is a cardinal 𝛿 <𝜅 with 𝑉𝛿 Σ𝑛𝑉𝜅 and the 𝛼-order theory of 𝑉𝛿 is the same as 𝑉𝜅.

Proof. One can do the same as above, since 𝑉𝜆 can see that 𝑉𝜅 has the 𝛼-order theory that it does, while also agreeing on Σ𝑛 truth with 𝑉𝜆, so 𝑉𝜅 will agree that there should be such a cardinal 𝛿 <𝜅.

Definition. We say that a cardinal is totally otherworldly, if it is otherworldly to arbitrarily large ordinals. It is otherworldly beyond 𝜃, if it is otherworldly to some ordinal larger than 𝜃. It is otherworldly up to 𝛿, if it is otherworldly to ordinals cofinal in 𝛿.

Theorem. Every inaccessible cardinal 𝛿 is a limit of otherworldly cardinals that are each otherworldly up to and to 𝛿.

Proof. If 𝛿 is inaccessible, then a simple Löwenheim-Skolem construction shows that 𝑉𝜅 is the union of a continuous elementary chain 𝑉𝜅0𝑉𝜅1𝑉𝜅𝛼𝑉𝜅 Each of the cardinals 𝜅𝛼 arising on this chain is otherworldly up to and to 𝛿.

Theorem. Every totally otherworldly cardinal is Σ2 correct, meaning 𝑉𝜅 Σ2𝑉. Consequently, every totally otherworldly cardinal is larger than the least measurable cardinal, if it exists, and larger than the least superstrong cardinal, if it exists, and larger than the least huge cardinal, if it exists.

Proof. Every Σ2 assertion is locally verifiable in the 𝑉𝛼 hierarchy, in that it is equivalent to an assertion of the form 𝜂𝑉𝜂 𝜓 (for more information, see my post about Local properties in set theory). Thus, every true Σ2 assertion is revealed inside any sufficiently large 𝑉𝜆, and so if 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 for arbitrarily large 𝜆, then 𝑉𝜅 will agree on those truths.

I was a little confused at first about how two totally otherwordly cardinals interact, but now everything is clear with this next result. (Thanks to Hanul Jeon for his helpful comment below.)

Theorem. If 𝜅 <𝛿 are both totally otherworldly, then 𝜅 is otherworldly up to 𝛿, and hence totally otherworldly in 𝑉𝛿.

Proof. Since 𝛿 is totally otherworldly, it is Σ2 correct. Since for every 𝛼 <𝛿 the cardinal 𝜅 is otherworldly beyond 𝛼, meaning 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 for some 𝜆 >𝛼, then since this is a Σ2 feature of 𝜅, it must already be true inside 𝑉𝛿. So such a 𝜆 can be found below 𝛿, and so 𝜅 is otherworldly up to 𝛿.

Theorem. If 𝜅 is totally otherworldly, then 𝜅 is a limit of otherworldly cardinals, and indeed, a limit of otherworldly cardinals having the same theory as 𝑉𝜅.

Proof. Assume 𝜅 is totally otherworldly, let 𝑇 be the theory of 𝑉𝜅, and consider any 𝛼 <𝜅. Since there is an otherworldly cardinal above 𝛼 with theory 𝑇, namely 𝜅, and because this is a Σ2 fact about 𝛼 and 𝑇, it follows that there must be such a cardinal above 𝛼 inside 𝑉𝜅. So 𝜅 is a limit of otherworldly cardinals with the same theory as 𝑉𝜅.

The results above show that the consistency strength of the hypotheses are ordered as follows, with strict increases in consistency strength as you go up (assuming consistency):

  • ZFC + there is an inaccessible cardinal
  • ZFC + there is a proper class of totally otherworldly cardinals
  • ZFC + there is a totally otherworldly cardinal
  • ZFC + there is a proper class of otherworldly cardinals
  • ZFC + there is an otherworldly cardinal
  • ZFC + there is a proper class of worldly cardinals
  • ZFC + there is a worldly cardinal
  • ZFC + there is a transitive model of ZFC
  • ZFC + Con(ZFC)
  • ZFC

We might consider the natural strengthenings of otherworldliness, where one wants 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 where 𝜆 is itself otherworldly. That is, 𝜅 is the beginning of an elementary chain of three models, not just two. This is different from having merely that 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆 and 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜂 for some 𝜂 >𝜆, because perhaps 𝑉𝜆 is not elementary in 𝑉𝜂, even though 𝑉𝜅 is. Extending successively is a more demanding requirement.

One then naturally wants longer and longer chains, and ultimately we find ourselves considering various notions of rank in the rank elementary forest, which is the relation 𝜅 𝜆 𝑉𝜅 𝑉𝜆. The otherworldly cardinals are simply the non-maximal nodes in this order, while it will be interesting to consider the nodes that can be extended to longer elementary chains.