Giorgio Audrito, PhD 2016, University of Torino

Dr. Giorgio Audrito has successfully defended his dissertation, “Generic large cardinals and absoluteness,” at the University of Torino under the supervision of Matteo Viale.

The dissertation Examing Board consisted of myself (serving as Presidente), Alessandro Andretta and Sean Cox.  The defense took place March 2, 2016.

Giorgio Audrito defense (small)

The dissertation was impressive, introducing (in joint work with Matteo Viale) the iterated resurrection axioms RAα(Γ) for a forcing class Γ, which extend the idea of the resurrection axioms from my work with Thomas Johnstone, The resurrection axioms and uplifting cardinals, by making successive extensions of the same type, forming the resurrection game, and insisting that that the resurrection player have a winning strategy with game value α. A similar iterative game idea underlies the (α)-uplifting cardinals, from which the consistency of the iterated resurrection axioms can be proved. A final chapter of the dissertation (joint with Silvia Steila), develops the notion of C-systems of filters, generalizing the more familiar concepts of extenders and towers.

Upward closure and amalgamation in the generic multiverse of a countable model of set theory

[bibtex key=Hamkins2016:UpwardClosureAndAmalgamationInTheGenericMultiverse]

Abstract. I prove several theorems concerning upward closure and amalgamation in the generic multiverse of a countable transitive model of set theory. Every such model W has forcing extensions W[c] and W[d] by adding a Cohen real, which cannot be amalgamated in any further extension, but some nontrivial forcing notions have all their extensions amalgamable. An increasing chain W[G0]W[G1] has an upper bound W[H] if and only if the forcing had uniformly bounded essential size in W. Every chain WW[c0]W[c1] of extensions adding Cohen reals is bounded above by W[d] for some W-generic Cohen real d.

This article is based upon I talk I gave at the conference on Recent Developments in Axiomatic Set Theory at the Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences (RIMS) at Kyoto University, Japan in September, 2015, and I am extremely grateful to my Japanese hosts, especially Toshimichi Usuba, for supporting my research visit there and also at the CTFM conference at Tokyo Institute of Technology just preceding it. This article includes material adapted from section section 2 of Set-theoretic geology, joint with G. Fuchs, myself and J. Reitz, and also includes a theorem that was proved in a series of conversations I had with Giorgio Venturi at the Young Set Theory Workshop 2011 in Bonn and continuing at the London 2011 summer school on set theory at Birkbeck University London.

The rearrangement number: how many rearrangements of a series suffice to verify absolute convergence? Vassar Math Colloquium, November 2015

This will be a talk for the Mathematics Colloquium at Vassar College, November 10, 2015, tea at 4:00 pm, talk at 4:15 pm, Rockefeller Hall 310

Abstract. The Riemann rearrangement theorem asserts that a series nan is absolutely convergent if and only if every rearrangement nap(n) of it is convergent, and furthermore, any conditionally convergent series can be rearranged so as to converge to any desired extended real value. How many rearrangements p suffice to test for absolute convergence in this way? The rearrangement number, a new cardinal characteristic of the continuum introduced just recently, is the smallest size of a family of permutations, such that whenever the convergence and value of a convergent series is invariant by all these permutations, then it is absolutely convergent. The exact value of the rearrangement number turns out to be independent of the axioms of set theory. In this talk, I shall place the rearrangement number into a discussion of cardinal characteristics of the continuum, including an elementary introduction to the continuum hypothesis and an account of Freiling’s axiom of symmetry.

This talk is based in part on current joint work with Andreas Blass, Will Brian, myself, Michael Hardy and Paul Larson.

My Lecture Notes are available. 

The rearrangement number, CUNY set theory seminar, November 2015

This will be a talk for the CUNY Set Theory Seminar on November 6, 2015.

The Riemann rearrangement theorem states that a convergent real series nan is absolutely convergent if and only if the value of the sum is invariant under all rearrangements nap(n) by any permutation p on the natural numbers; furthermore, if the series is merely conditionally convergent, then one may find rearrangements for which the new sum nap(n) has any desired (extended) real value or which becomes non-convergent.  In recent joint work with Andreas Blass, Will Brian, myself, Michael Hardy and Paul Larson, based on an exchange in reply to a Hardy’s MathOverflow question on the topic, we investigate the minimal size of a family of permutations that can be used in this manner to test an arbitrary convergent series for absolute convergence.

Specifically, we define the rearrangement number rr (“double-r”), a new cardinal characteristic of the continuum, to be the smallest cardinality of a set P of permutations of the natural numbers, such that if a convergent real series nan remains convergent and with the same sum after all rearrangements nap(n) by a permutation pP, then it is absolutely convergent. The corresponding rearrangement number for sums, denoted rrΣ, is the smallest cardinality of a family P of permutations, such that if a series nan is conditionally convergent, then there is a rearrangement nap(n), by some permutation pP, which converges to a different sum. We investigate the basic properties of these numbers, and explore their relations with other cardinal characteristics of the continuum. Our main results are that brrnon(M), that drrΣ, and that b<rr is relatively consistent.

MathOverflow question | CUNY Set Theory Seminar

Being HOD-of-a-set is invariant throughout the generic multiverse

Iowa State Capitol - Law Library _ Flickr - Photo Sharing!The axiom V=HOD, introduced by Gödel, asserts that every set is ordinal definable. This axiom has a subtler foundational aspect than might at first be expected. The reason is that the general concept of “object x is definable using parameter p” is not in general first-order expressible in set theory; it is of course a second-order property, which makes sense only relative to a truth predicate, and by Tarski’s theorem, we can have no first-order definable truth predicate. Thus, the phrase “definable using ordinal parameters” is not directly meaningful in the first-order language of set theory without further qualification or explanation. Fortunately, however, it is a remarkable fact that when we allow definitions to use arbitrary ordinal parameters, as we do with HOD, then we can in fact make such qualifications in such a way that the axiom becomes first-order expressible in set theory. Specifically, we say officially that V=HOD holds, if for every set x, there is an ordinal θ with xVθ, for which which x is definable by some formula ψ(x) in the structure Vθ, using ordinal parameters. Since Vθ is a set, we may freely make reference to first-order truth in Vθ without requiring any truth predicate in V. Certainly any such x as this is also ordinal-definable in V, since we may use θ and the Gödel-code of ψ also as parameters, and note that x is the unique object such that it is in Vθ and satisfies ψ in Vθ. (Note that inside an ω-nonstandard model of set theory, we may really need to use ψ as a parameter, since it may be nonstandard, and x may not be definable in Vθ using a meta-theoretically standard natural number; but fortunately, the Gödel code of a formula is an integer, which is still an ordinal, and this issue is the key to the issue.) Conversely, if x is definable in V using formula φ(x,α) with ordinal parameters α, then it follows by the reflection theorem that x is defined by φ(x,α) inside some Vθ. So this formulation of V=HOD is expressible and exactly captures the desired second-order property that every set is ordinal-definable.

Consider next the axiom V=HOD(b), asserting that every set is definable from ordinal parameters and parameter b. Officially, as before, V=HOD(b) asserts that for every x, there is an ordinal θ, formula ψ and ordinals α<θ, such that x is the unique object in Vθ for which Vθ,ψ(x,α,b), and the reflection argument shows again that this way of defining the axiom exactly captures the intended idea.

The axiom I actually want to focus on is b(V=HOD(b)), asserting that the universe is HOD of a set. (I assume ZFC in the background theory.) It turns out that this axiom is constant throughout the generic multiverse.

Theorem. The assertion b(V=HOD(b)) is forcing invariant.

  • If it holds in V, then it continues to hold in every set forcing extension of V.
  • If it holds in V, then it holds in every ground of V.

Thus, the truth of this axiom is invariant throughout the generic multiverse.

Proof. Suppose that ZFC+V=HOD(b), and V[G] is a forcing extension of V by generic filter GPV. By the ground-model definability theorem, it follows that V is definable in V[G] from parameter P(P)V. Thus, using this parameter, as well as b and additional ordinal parameters, we can define in V[G] any particular object in V. Since this includes all the P-names used to form V[G], it follows that V[G]=HOD(b,P(P)V,G), and so V[G] is HOD of a set, as desired.

Conversely, suppose that W is a ground of V, so that V=W[G] for some W-generic filter GPW, and V=HOD(b) for some set b. Let b˙ be a name for which b˙G=b. Every object xW is definable in W[G] from b and ordinal parameters α, so there is some formula ψ for which x is unique such that ψ(x,b,α). Thus, there is some condition pP such that x is unique such that pψ(xˇ,b˙,αˇ). If pββ<|P| is a fixed enumeration of P in W, then p=pβ for some ordinal β, and we may therefore define x in W using ordinal parameters, along with b˙ and the fixed enumeration of P. So W thinks the universe is HOD of a set, as desired.

Since the generic multiverse is obtained by iteratively moving to forcing extensions to grounds, and each such movement preserves the axiom, it follows that b(V=HOD(b)) is constant throughout the generic multiverse. QED

Theorem. If V=HOD(b), then there is a forcing extension V[G] in which V=HOD holds.

Proof. We are working in ZFC. Suppose that V=HOD(b). We may assume b is a set of ordinals, since such sets can code any given set. Consider the following forcing iteration: first add a Cohen real c, and then perform forcing G that codes c, P(ω)V and b into the GCH pattern at uncountable cardinals, and then perform self-encoding forcing H above that coding, coding also G (see my paper on Set-theoretic geology for further details on self-encoding forcing). In the final model V[c][G][H], therefore, the objects c, b, P(ω)V, G and H are all definable without parameters. Since VV[c][G][H] has a closure point at ω, it satisfies the ω1-approximation and cover properties, and therefore the class V is definable in V[c][G][H] using P(ω)V as a parameter. Since this parameter is itself definable without parameters, it follows that V is parameter-free definable in V[c][G][H]. Since b is also definable there, it follows that every element of HOD(b)V=V is ordinal-definable in V[c][G][H]. And since c, G and H are also definable without parameters, we have V[c][G][H]V=HOD, as desired. QED

Corollary. The following are equivalent.

  1. The universe is HOD of a set: b(V=HOD(b)).
  2. Somewhere in the generic multiverse, the universe is HOD of a set.
  3. Somewhere in the generic multiverse, the axiom V=HOD holds.
  4. The axiom V=HOD is forceable.

Proof. This is an immediate consequence of the previous theorems. 14321. QED

Corollary. The axiom V=HOD, if true, even if true anywhere in the generic multiverse, is a switch.

Proof. A switch is a statement such that both it and its negation are necessarily possible by forcing; that is, in every set forcing extension, one can force the statement to be true and also force it to be false. We can always force V=HOD to fail, simply by adding a Cohen real. If V=HOD is true, then by the first theorem, every forcing extension has V=HOD(b) for some b, in which case V=HOD remains forceable, by the second theorem. QED

Upward countable closure in the generic multiverse of forcing to add a Cohen real

I’d like to discuss my theorem that the collection of models M[c] obtained by adding an M-generic Cohen real c over a fixed countable transitive model of set theory M is upwardly countably closed, in the sense that every increasing countable chain has an upper bound.

I proved this theorem back in 2011, while at the Young Set Theory Workshop in Bonn and continuing at the London summer school on set theory, in a series of conversations with Giorgio Venturi. The argument has recently come up again in various discussions, and so let me give an account of it.

We consider the collection of all forcing extensions of a fixed countable transitive model M of ZFC by the forcing to add a Cohen real, models of the form M[c], and consider the question of whether every countable increasing chain of these models has an upper bound. The answer is yes!  (Actually, Giorgio wants to undertake forcing constructions by forcing over this collection of models to add a generic upward directed system of models; it follows from this theorem that this forcing is countably closed.) This theorem fits into the theme of my earlier post, Upward closure in the toy multiverse of all countable models of set theory, where similar theorems are proved, but not this one exactly.

Theorem. For any countable transitive model MZFC, the collection of all forcing extensions M[c] by adding an M-generic Cohen real is upward-countably closed. That is, for any countable tower of such forcing extensions
M[c0]M[c1]M[cn],
we may find an M-generic Cohen real d such that M[cn]M[d] for every natural number n.

Proof. Suppose that we have such a tower of forcing extensions M[c0]M[c1], and so on. Note that if M[b]M[c] for M-generic Cohen reals b and c, then M[c] is a forcing extension of M[b] by a quotient of the Cohen-real forcing. But since the Cohen forcing itself has a countable dense set, it follows that all such quotients also have a countable dense set, and so M[c] is actually M[b][b1] for some M[b]-generic Cohen real b1. Thus, we may view the tower as having the form:
M[b0]M[b0×b1]M[b0×b1××bn],
where now it follows that any finite collection of the reals bi are mutually M-generic.

Of course, we cannot expect in general that the real bnn<ω is M-generic for Add(ω,ω), since this real may be very badly behaved. For example, the sequence of first-bits of the bn’s may code a very naughty real z, which cannot be added by forcing over M at all. So in general, we cannot allow that this sequence is added to the limit model M[d]. (See further discussion in my post Upward closure in the toy multiverse of all countable models of set theory.)

We shall instead undertake a construction by making finitely many changes to each real bn, resulting in a real dn, in such a way that the resulting combined real d=ndn is M-generic for the forcing to add ω-many Cohen reals, which is of course isomorphic to adding just one. To do this, let’s get a little more clear with our notation. We regard each bn as an element of Cantor space 2ω, that is, an infinite binary sequence, and the corresponding filter associated with this real is the collection of finite initial segments of bn, which will be an M-generic filter through the partial order of finite binary sequences 2<ω, which is one of the standard isomorphic copies of Cohen forcing. We will think of d as a binary function on the plane d:ω×ω2, where the nth slice dn is the corresponding function ω2 obtained by fixing the first coordinate to be n.

Now, we enumerate the countably many open dense subsets for the forcing to add a Cohen real ω×ω2 as D0, D1, and so on. There are only countably many such dense sets, because M is countable. Now, we construct d in stages. Before stage n, we will have completely specified dk for k<n, and we also may be committed to a finite condition pn1 in the forcing to add ω many Cohen reals. We consider the dense set Dn. We may factor Add(ω,ω) as Add(ω,n)×Add(ω,[n,ω)). Since d0××dn1 is actually M-generic (since these are finite modifications of the corresponding bk’s, which are mutually M-generic, it follows that there is some finite extension of our condition pn1 to a condition pnDn, which is compatible with d0××dn1. Let dn be the same as bn, except finitely modified to be compatible with pn. In this way, our final real ndn will contain all the conditions pn, and therefore be M-generic for Add(ω,ω), yet every bn will differ only finitely from dn and hence be an element of M[d]. So we have M[b0][bn]M[d], and we have found our upper bound. QED

Notice that the real d we construct is not only M-generic, but also M[cn]-generic for every n.

My related post, Upward closure in the toy multiverse of all countable models of set theory, which is based on material in my paper Set-theoretic geology, discusses some similar results.

Upward closure in the generic multiverse of a countable model of set theory, RIMS 2015, Kyoto, Japan

Philosophers Walk Kyoto Japan (summer)This will be a talk for the conference Recent Developments in Axiomatic Set Theory at the Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences (RIMS) in Kyoto, Japan, September 16-18, 2015.

Abstract. Consider a countable model of set theory amongst its forcing extensions, the ground models of those extensions, the extensions of those models and so on, closing under the operations of forcing extension and ground model.  This collection is known as the generic multiverse of the original model.  I shall present a number of upward-oriented closure results in this context. For example, for a long-known negative result, it is a fun exercise to construct forcing extensions M[c] and M[d] of a given countable model of set theory M, each by adding an M-generic Cohen real, which cannot be amalgamated, in the sense that there is no common extension model N that contains both M[c] and M[d] and has the same ordinals as M. On the positive side, however, any increasing sequence of extensions M[G0]M[G1]M[G2], by forcing of uniformly bounded size in M, has an upper bound in a single forcing extension M[G]. (Note that one cannot generally have the sequence Gnn<ω in M[G], so a naive approach to this will fail.)  I shall discuss these and related results, many of which appear in the “brief upward glance” section of my recent paper:  G. Fuchs, J. D. Hamkins and J. Reitz, Set-theoretic geology.


Erin Carmody

Erin Carmody successfully defended her dissertation under my supervision at the CUNY Graduate Center on April 24, 2015, and she earned her Ph.D. degree in May, 2015. Her dissertation follows the theme of killing them softly, proving many theorems of the form: given κ with large cardinal property A, there is a forcing extension in which κ no longer has property A, but still has large cardinal property B, which is very slightly weaker than A. Thus, she aims to enact very precise reductions in large cardinal strength of a given cardinal or class of large cardinals. In addition, as a part of the project, she developed transfinite meta-ordinal extensions of the degrees of hyper-inaccessibility and hyper-Mahloness, giving notions such as (Ωω2+5+Ω3ω12+Ω+2)-inaccessible among others.

Erin Carmody

G+ profile | math genealogy | MathOverflow profileNY Logic profilearχiv

Erin Carmody, “Forcing to change large cardinal strength,”  Ph.D. dissertation for The Graduate Center of the City University of New York, May, 2015.  arχiv | PDF

Erin has accepted a professorship at Nebreska Wesleyan University for.the 2015-16 academic year.


 

Erin is also an accomplished artist, who has had art shows of her work in New York, and she has pieces for sale. Much of her work has an abstract or mathematical aspect, while some pieces exhibit a more emotional or personal nature. My wife and I have two of Erin’s paintings in our collection:
OceanIMG_0597

The weakly compact embedding property, Apter-Gitik celebration, CMU 2015

This will be a talk at the Conference in honor of Arthur W. Apter and Moti Gitik at Carnegie Mellon University, May 30-31, 2015.  I am pleased to be a part of this conference in honor of the 60th birthdays of two mathematicians whom I admire very much.

Moti GitikArthur W. Apter

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Abstract. The weakly compact embedding property for a cardinal κ is the assertion that for every transitive set M of size κ with κM, there is a transitive set N and an elementary embedding j:MN with critical point κ. When κ is inaccessible, this property is one of many equivalent characterizations of κ being weakly compact, along with the weakly compact extension property, the tree property, the weakly compact filter property and many others. When κ is not inaccessible, however, these various properties are no longer equivalent to each other, and it is interesting to sort out the relations between them. In particular, I shall consider the embedding property and these other properties in the case when κ is not necessarily inaccessible, including interesting instances of the embedding property at cardinals below the continuum, with relations to cardinal characteristics of the continuum.

This is joint work with Brent Cody, Sean Cox, myself and Thomas Johnstone.

Slides | Article | Conference web site

Carnegie Mellon University, College of Fine Arts

Upward closure in the toy multiverse of all countable models of set theory

The Multiverse by KaeltykThe toy multiverse of all countable models of set theory is upward closed under countably many successive forcing extensions of bounded size…

I’d like to explain a topic from my recent paper

G. Fuchs, J. D. Hamkins, J. ReitzSet-theoretic geology, to appear in the Annals of Pure and Applied Logic.

We just recently made the final revisions, and the paper is available if you follow the title link through to the arxiv. Most of the geology article proceeds from a downward-oriented focus on forcing, looking from a universe V down to its grounds, the inner models W over which V might have arisen by forcing V=W[G]. Thus, the set-theoretic geology project arrives at deeper and deeper grounds and the mantle and inner mantle concepts.

One section of the paper, however, has an upward-oriented focus, namely, §2 A brief upward glance, and it is that material about which I’d like to write here, because I find it to be both interesting and comparatively accessible, but also because the topic proceeds from a different perspective than the rest of the geology paper, and so I am a little fearful that it may get lost there.

First is the observation that I first heard from W. Hugh Woodin in the early 1990s.

Observation. If W is a countable model of ZFC set theory, then there are forcing extensions W[c] and W[d], both obtained by adding a Cohen real, which are non-amalgamable in the sense that there can be no model of ZFC with the same ordinals as W containing both W[c] and W[d]. Thus, the family of forcing extensions of W is not upward directed.

Proof. Since W is countable, let z be a real coding the entirety of W. Enumerate the dense subsets Dnn<ω of the Cohen forcing Add(ω,1) in W. We construct c and d in stages. We begin by letting c0 be any element of D0. Let d0 consist of exactly as many 0s as |c0|, followed by a 1, followed by z(0), and then extended to an element of D0. Continuing, cn+1 extends cn by adding 0s until the length of dn, and then a 1, and then extending into Dn+1; and dn+1 extends dn by adding 0s to the length of cn+1, then a 1, then z(n), then extending into Dn+1. Let c=cn and d=dn. Since we met all the dense sets in W, we know that c and d are W-generic Cohen reals, and so we may form the forcing extensions W[c] and W[d]. But if WUZFC and both c and d are in U, then in U we may reconstruct the map ncn,dn, by giving attention to the blocks of 0s in c and d. From this map, we may reconstruct z in U, which reveals all the ordinals of W to be countable, a contradiction if U and W have the same ordinals. QED

Most of the results here concern forcing extensions of an arbitrary countable model of set theory, which of course includes the case of ill-founded models. Although there is no problem with forcing extensions of ill-founded models, when properly carried out, the reader may prefer to focus on the case of countable transitive models for the results in this section, and such a perspective will lose very little of the point of our observations.

The method of the observation above is easily generalized to produce three W-generic Cohen reals c0, c1 and c2, such that any two of them can be amalgamated, but the three of them cannot. More generally:

Observation. If W is a countable model of ZFC set theory, then for any finite n there are W-generic Cohen reals c0,c1,,cn1, such that any proper subset of them are mutually W-generic, so that one may form the generic extension W[c], provided that c omits at least one ci, but there is no forcing extension W[G] simultaneously extending all W[ci] for i<n. In particular, the sequence c0,c1,,cn1 cannot be added by forcing over W.

Let us turn now to infinite linearly ordered sequences of forcing extensions. We show first in the next theorem and subsequent observation that one mustn’t ask for too much; but nevertheless, after that we shall prove the surprising positive result, that any increasing sequence of forcing extensions over a countable model W, with forcing of uniformly bounded size, is bounded above by a single forcing extension W[G].

Theorem. If W is a countable model of ZFC, then there is an increasing sequence of set-forcing extensions of W having no upper bound in the generic multiverse of W. W[G0]W[G1]W[Gn]

Proof. Since W is countable, there is an increasing sequence γnn<ω of ordinals that is cofinal in the ordinals of W. Let Gn be W-generic for the collapse forcing Coll(ω,γn), as defined in W. (By absorbing the smaller forcing, we may arrange that W[Gn] contains Gm for m<n.) Since every ordinal of W is eventually collapsed, there can be no set-forcing extension of W, and indeed, no model with the same ordinals as W, that contains every W[Gn]. QED

But that was cheating, of course, since the sequence of forcing notions is not even definable in W, as the class {γnn<ω} is not a class of W. A more intriguing question would be whether this phenomenon can occur with forcing notions that constitute a set in W, or (equivalently, actually) whether it can occur using always the same poset in W. For example, if W[c0]W[c0][c1]W[c0][c1][c2] is an increasing sequence of generic extensions of W by adding Cohen reals, then does it follow that there is a set-forcing extension W[G] of W with W[c0][cn]W[G] for every n? For this, we begin by showing that one mustn’t ask for too much:

Observation. If W is a countable model of ZFC, then there is a sequence of forcing extensions WW[c0]W[c0][c1]W[c0][c1][c2], adding a Cohen real at each step, such that there is no forcing extension of W containing the sequence cnn<ω.

Proof. Let dnn<ω be any W-generic sequence for the forcing to add ω many Cohen reals over W. Let z be any real coding the ordinals of W. Let us view these reals as infinite binary sequences. Define the real cn to agree with dn on all digits except the initial digit, and set cn(0)=z(n). That is, we make a single-bit change to each dn, so as to code one additional bit of z. Since we have made only finitely many changes to each dn, it follows that cn is an W-generic Cohen real, and also W[c0][cn]=W[d0][dn]. Thus, we have WW[c0]W[c0][c1]W[c0][c1][c2], adding a generic Cohen real at each step. But there can be no forcing extension of W containing cnn<ω, since any such extension would have the real z, revealing all the ordinals of W to be countable. QED

We can modify the construction to allow z to be W-generic, but collapsing some cardinals of W. For example, for any cardinal δ of W, we could let z be W-generic for the collapse of δ. Then, if we construct the sequence cnn<ω as above, but inside W[z], we get a sequence of Cohen real extensions WW[c0]W[c0][c1]W[c0][c1][c2] such that W[cnn<ω]=W[z], which collapses δ.

But of course, the question of whether the models W[c0][c1][cn] have an upper bound is not the same question as whether one can add the sequence cnn<ω, since an upper bound may not have this sequence. And in fact, this is exactly what occurs, and we have a surprising positive result:

Theorem. Suppose that W is a countable model of \ZFC, and W[G0]W[G1]W[Gn] is an increasing sequence of forcing extensions of W, with GnQnW being W-generic. If the cardinalities of the Qn’s in W are bounded in W, then there is a set-forcing extension W[G] with W[Gn]W[G] for all n<ω.

Proof. Let us first make the argument in the special case that we have WW[g0]W[g0][g1]W[g0][g1][gn], where each gn is generic over the prior model for forcing QnW. That is, each extension W[g0][g1][gn] is obtained by product forcing Q0××Qn over W, and the gn are mutually W-generic. Let δ be a regular cardinal with each Qn having size at most δ, built with underlying set a subset of δ. In W, let θ=2δ, let Rαα<θ enumerate all posets of size at most δ, with unbounded repetition, and let P=α<θRα be the finite-support product of these posets. Since each factor is δ+-c.c., it follows that the product is δ+-c.c. Since W is countable, we may build a filter HP that is W-generic. In fact, we may find such a filter HP that meets every dense set in n<ωW[g0][g1][gn], since this union is also countable. In particular, H and g0××gn are mutually W-generic for every n<ω. The filter H is determined by the filters HαRα that it adds at each coordinate.

Next comes the key step. Externally to W, we may find an increasing sequence θnn<ω of ordinals cofinal in θ, such that Rθn=Qn. This is possible because the posets are repeated unboundedly, and θ is countable in V. Let us modify the filter H by surgery to produce a new filter H, by changing H at the coordinates θn to use gn rather than Hθn. That is, let Hθn=gn and otherwise Hα=Hα, for α{θnn<ω}. It is clear that H is still a filter on P. We claim that H is W-generic. To see this, suppose that AP is any maximal antichain in W. By the δ+-chain condition and the fact that cof(θ)W>δ, it follows that the conditions in A have support bounded by some γ<θ. Since the θn are increasing and cofinal in θ, only finitely many of them lay below γ, and we may suppose that there is some largest θm below γ. Let H be the filter derived from H by performing the surgical modifications only on the coordinates θ0,,θm. Thus, H and H agree on all coordinates below γ. By construction, we had ensured that H and g0××gm are mutually generic over W for the forcing P×Q0××Qm. This poset has an automorphism swapping the latter copies of Qi with their copy at θi in P, and this automorphism takes the W-generic filter H×g0××gm exactly to H×Hθ0××Hθm. In particular, H is W-generic for P, and so H meets the maximal antichain A. Since H and H agree at coordinates below γ, it follows that H also meets A. In summary, we have proved that H is W-generic for P, and so W[H] is a set-forcing extension of W. By design, each gn appears at coordinate θn in H, and so W[g0][gn]W[H] for every n<ω, as desired.

Finally, we reduce the general case to this special case. Suppose that W[G0]W[G1]W[Gn] is an increasing sequence of forcing extensions of W, with GnQnW being W-generic and each Qn of size at most κ in W. By the standard facts surrounding finite iterated forcing, we may view each model as a forcing extension of the previous model W[Gn+1]=W[Gn][Hn], where Hn is W[Gn]-generic for the corresponding quotient forcing Qn/Gn in W[Gn]. Let gColl(ω,κ) be nW[Gn]-generic for the collapse of κ, so that it is mutually generic with every Gn. Thus, we have the increasing sequence of extensions W[g][G0]W[g][G1], where we have added g to each model. Since each Qn is countable in W[g], it is forcing equivalent there to the forcing to add a Cohen real. Furthermore, the quotient forcing Qn/Gn is also forcing equivalent in W[g][Gn] to adding a Cohen real. Thus, W[g][Gn+1]=W[g][Gn][Hn]=W[g][Gn][hn], for some W[g][Gn]-generic Cohen real hn. Unwrapping this recursion, we have W[g][Gn+1]=W[g][G0][h1][hn], and consequently W[g]W[g][G0]W[g][G0][h1]W[g][G0][h1][h2], which places us into the first case of the proof, since this is now product forcing rather than iterated forcing. QED

Definition. A collection {W[Gn]n<ω} of forcing extensions of W is finitely amalgamable over W if for every n<ω there is a forcing extension W[H] with W[Gm]W[H] for all mn. It is amalgamable over W if there is W[H] such that W[Gn]W[H] for all n<ω.

The next corollary shows that we cannot improve the non-amalgamability result of the initial observation to the case of infinitely many Cohen reals, with all finite subsets amalgamable.

Corollary. If W is a countable model of ZFC and {W[Gn]n<ω} is a finitely amalgamable collection of forcing extensions of W, using forcing of bounded size in W, then this collection is fully amalgamable. That is, there is a forcing extension W[H] with W[Gn]W[H] for all n<ω.

Proof. Since the collection is finitely amalgamable, for each n<ω there is some W-generic K such that W[Gm]W[K] for all mn. Thus, we may form the minimal model W[G0][G1][Gn] between W and W[K], and thus W[G0][G1][Gn] is a forcing extension of W. We are thus in the situation of the theorem, with an increasing chain of forcing extensions. WW[G0]W[G0][G1]W[G0][G1][Gn] Therefore, by the theorem, there is a model W[H] containing all these extensions, and in particular, W[Gn]W[H], as desired. QED

Please go to the paper for more details and discussion.

When does every definable set have a definable member? CUNY Set Theory Seminar, October 2014

This will be a talk for the CUNY set theory seminar, October 10, 2014, 12pm  GC 6417.

Abstract. Although the concept of `being definable’ is not generally expressible in the language of set theory, it turns out that the models of ZF in which every definable nonempty set has a definable element are precisely the models of V=HOD.  Indeed, V=HOD is equivalent to the assertion merely that every Π2-definable set has an ordinal-definable element. Meanwhile, this is not true in the case of Σ2-definability, because every model of ZFC has a forcing extension satisfying VHOD in which every Σ2-definable set has an ordinal-definable element.

This is joint work with François G. Dorais and Emil Jeřábek, growing out of some questions and answers on MathOverflow, namely,

Definable collections without definable members
A question asked by Ashutosh five years ago, in which François and I gradually came upon the answer together.
Is it consistent that every definable set has a definable member?
A similar question asked last week by (anonymous) user38200
Can VHOD if every Σ2-definable set has an ordinal-definable member?
A question I had regarding the limits of an issue in my answer to the previous question.

In this talk, I shall present the answers to all these questions and place the results in the context of classical results on definability, including a review of basic concepts for graduate students.

Large cardinals need not be large in HOD

[bibtex key=ChengFriedmanHamkins2015:LargeCardinalsNeedNotBeLargeInHOD]

Abstract. We prove that large cardinals need not generally exhibit their large cardinal nature in HOD. For example, a supercompact cardinal κ need not be weakly compact in HOD, and there can be a proper class of supercompact cardinals in V, none of them weakly compact in HOD, with no supercompact cardinals in HOD. Similar results hold for many other types of large cardinals, such as measurable and strong cardinals.

In this article, we prove that large cardinals need not generally exhibit their large cardinal nature in HOD, the inner model of hereditarily ordinal-definable sets, and there can be a divergence in strength between the large cardinals of the ambient set-theoretic universe V and those of HOD. Our general theme concerns the questions:

Questions.

1. To what extent must a large cardinal in V exhibit its large cardinal properties in HOD?

2. To what extent does the existence of large cardinals in V imply the existence of large cardinals in HOD?

For large cardinal concepts beyond the weakest notions, we prove, the answers are generally negative. In Theorem 4, for example, we construct a model with a supercompact cardinal that is not weakly compact in HOD, and Theorem 9 extends this to a proper class of supercompact cardinals, none of which is weakly compact in HOD, thereby providing some strongly negative instances of (1). The same model has a proper class of supercompact cardinals, but no supercompact cardinals in HOD, providing a negative instance of (2). The natural common strengthening of these situations would be a model with a proper class of supercompact cardinals, but no weakly compact cardinals in HOD. We were not able to arrange that situation, however, and furthermore it would be ruled out by Conjecture 13, an intriguing positive instance of (2) recently proposed by W. Hugh Woodin, namely, that if there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a measurable cardinal in HOD. Many other natural possibilities, such as a proper class of measurable cardinals with no weakly compact cardinals in HOD, remain as open questions.

CUNY talkRutgers talk | Luminy talk

A common forcing extension obtained via different forcing notions

I’d like to write about the situation that occurs in set theory when a forcing extension V[G]=V[H] arises over a ground model V in two different ways simultaneously, using generic filters over two different forcing notions GB and HC. The general fact, stated in theorem 1, is that in this case, the two forcing notions are actually isomorphic on a cone BbCc, with the isomorphism carrying the one generic filter to the other. In other words, below these respective conditions b and c, the forcing notions and the respective generic filters are not actually different.

I have always assumed that this fact was part of the classical forcing folklore results, but it doesn’t seem to be mentioned explicitly in the usual forcing literature (it appears as lemma 25.5 in Jech’s book), and so I am writing an account of it here. Victoria Gitman and I have need of it in a current joint project. (Bob Solovay mentions in the comments below that the result is due to him, and provides a possible 1975 reference.)

Theorem 1. If V[G]=V[H], where GB and HC are V-generic filters on the complete Boolean algebras B and C, respectively, then there are conditions bB and cC such that Bb is isomorphic to Cc by an isomorphism carrying G to H.

The proof will also establish the following related result, concerning the situation where one extension is merely contained in the other.

Theorem 2. If V[H]V[G], where GB and HC are V-generic filters on the complete Boolean algebras B and C, respectively, then there are conditions bB and cC such that Cc is isomorphic to a complete subalgebra of Bb.

By Bb, where b is a condition in B (that is, a nonzero element of B), what I mean is the Boolean algebra consisting of the interval [0,b] in B, using relative complement ba as the negation of a. This is the complete Boolean algebra that arises when forcing with the conditions in B below b.

Proof: In order to prove theorem 2, let me assume at first only that V[H]V[G]. It follows that H=H˙G for some B-name H˙, and we may choose a condition bG forcing that H˙ is a Vˇ-generic filter on Cˇ.

I claim that there is some cH such that every dc has b[[dˇH˙]]B0. Note that every dH has [[dˇH˙]]G by the truth lemma, since H=H˙G, and so b[[dˇH˙]]B0 for dH. If cH forces that every d in the generic filter has that property, then indeed every dc has b[[dˇH˙]]B0 as claimed.
In other words, from the perspective of the B forcing, every dc has a nonzero possibility to be in H˙.

Define π:CcB by π(d)=b[[dˇH˙]]B. Using the fact that b forces that H˙ is a filter, it is straightforward to verify that

  • deπ(d)π(e), since if de and dH, then eH.
  • π(de)=π(d)π(e), since [[dˇH˙]][[eˇH˙]]=[[(be)ˇH˙]].
  • π(de)=π(d)π(e), since [[(de)ˇH˙]]=[[dˇH˙]][[eˇH˙]].

Thus, π is a Boolean algebra embedding of Cc into Bπ(c).

Let me argue that this embedding is a complete embedding. Suppose that a=A for some subset ACc with AV. Since H is V-generic, it follows that aH just in case H meets A. Thus, [[aˇH˙]]=[[xAˇxH˙]]=xA[[xˇH˙]], and so π(A)=xAπ(x), and so π is complete, as desired. This proves theorem 2.

To prove theorem 1, let me now assume fully that V[G]=V[H]. In this case, there is a C name G˙ for which G=G˙H. By strengthening b, we may assume without loss that b also forces that, that is, that b forces Γ=G˙ˇH˙, where Γ is the canonical B-name for the generic object, and G˙ˇ is the B-name of the C-name G˙. Let us also strengthen c to ensure that c forces G˙ is Vˇ-generic for Cˇ. For dc define π(d)=[[dˇH˙]]B as above, which provides a complete embedding of Cc to Bπ(c). I shall now argue that this embedding is dense below π(c). Suppose that aπ(c) in B. Since a forces aˇΓ and also cˇH˙, it must also force that there is some dc in H˙ that forces via C over Vˇ that aˇG˙. So there must really be some dc forcing aˇG˙. So π(d), which forces dˇH˙, will also force aˇG˙ˇH˙=Γ, and so π(d)BaˇΓ, which means π(d)a in B. Thus, the range of π on Cc is dense below π(c), and so π is a complete dense embedding of Cc to Bπ(c). Since these are complete Boolean algebras, this means that π is actually an isomorphism of Cc with Bπ(c), as desired.

Finally, note that if dH below c, then since H=H˙G, it follows that [[dˇH˙]]G, which is to say π(d)G, and so π carries H to G on these cones. So π1 is the isomorphism stated in theorem 1.QED

Finally, I note that one cannot get rid of the need to restrict to cones, since it could be that B and C are the lottery sums of a common forcing notion, giving rise to V[G]=V[H], together with totally different non-isomorphic forcing notions below some other incompatible conditions. So we cannot expect to prove that BC, and are content to get merely that BbCc, an isomorphism below respective conditions.

Large cardinals need not be large in HOD, International Workshop on Set Theory, CIRM, Luminy, September 2014

I shall speak at the 13th International Workshop on Set Theory, held at the CIRM Centre International de Rencontres Mathématiques in Luminy near Marseille, France, September 29 to October 3, 2014. 

Abstract.  I shall prove that large cardinals need not generally exhibit their large cardinal nature in HOD. For example, a supercompact cardinal need not be weakly compact in HOD, and there can be a proper class of supercompact cardinals in V, none of them weakly compact in HOD, with no supercompact cardinals in HOD. Similar results hold for many other types of large cardinals, such as measurable and strong cardinals. There are many open questions.

This talk will include joint work with Cheng Yong and Sy-David Friedman.

Article | Participants | Slides

Large cardinal indestructibility: two slick new proofs of prior results

I’ve recently found two slick new proofs of some of my prior results on indestructibility, using the idea of an observation of Arthur Apter’s.  What he had noted is:

Observation. (Apter [1])  If κ is a Laver indestructible supercompact cardinal, then VκHOD.  Indeed, Vκ satisfies the continuum coding axiom CCA.

Proof. The continuum coding axiom asserts that every set of ordinals is coded into the GCH pattern (it follows that they are each coded unboundedly often). If xκ is any bounded set of ordinals, then let Q be the forcing to code x into the GCH pattern at regular cardinals directly above κ. This forcing is <κ-directed closed, and so by our assumption, κ remains supercompact and in particular Σ2-reflecting in the extension V[G]. Since x is coded into the GCH pattern of V[G], it follows by reflection that Vκ=V[G]κ must also think that x is coded, and so VκCCA. QED

First, what I noticed is that this immediately implies that small forcing ruins indestructibility:

Theorem. (Hamkins, Shelah [2], Hamkins [3]) After any nontrivial forcing of size less than κ, the cardinal κ is no longer indestructibly supercompact, nor even indestructibly Σ2-reflecting.

Proof.  Nontrivial small forcing V[g] will add a new set of ordinals below κ, which will not be coded unboundedly often into the continuum function of V[g], and so V[g]κ will not satisfy the CCA.  Hence, κ will not be indestructibly Σ2-reflecting there. QED

This argument can be seen as essentially related to Shelah’s 1998 argument, given in [2].

Second, I also noticed that a similar idea can be used to prove:

Theorem. (Bagaria, Hamkins, Tsaprounis, Usuba [4])  Superstrong and other large cardinals are never Laver indestructible.

Proof.  Suppose the superstrongness of κ is indestructible. It follows by the observation that Vκ satisfies the continuum coding axiom. Now force to add a V-generic Cohen subset Gκ.  If κ were superstrong in V[G], then there would be j:V[G]M with V[G]j(κ)=Mj(κ). Since G is not coded into the continuum function, Mj(κ) does not satisfy the CCA.  This contradicts the elementarity Vκ=V[G]κMj(κ). QED

The argument shows that even the Σ3-extendibility of κ is never Laver indestructible.

I would note, however, that the slick proof does not achieve the stronger result of [4], which is that superstrongness is never indestructible even by Add(κ,1), and that after forcing to add a Cohen subset to κ (among any of many other common forcing notions), the cardinal κ is never Σ3-extendible (and hence not superstrong, not weakly superstrong, and so on).  The slick proof above uses indestructibility by the coding forcing to get the CCA in Vκ, and it is not clear how one would argue that way to get these stronger results of [4].

[1] Arthur W. Apter and Shoshana Friedman. HOD-supercompactness, inestructibility, and level-by-level equivalence, to appear in Bulletin of the Polish Academy of Sciences (Mathematics).

[2] Joel David Hamkins, Saharon Shelah, Superdestructibility: A Dual to Laver’s Indestructibility,  J. Symbolic Logic, Volume 63, Issue 2 (1998), 549-554.

[3] Joel David Hamkins, Small forcing makes any cardinal superdestructible, J. Symbolic Logic, 63 (1998).

[4] Joan Bagaria, Joel David Hamkins, Konstantinos Tsaprounis, Toshimichi Usuba, Superstrong and other large cardinals are never Laver indestructible, to appear in the Archive of Math Logic (special issue in memory of Richard Laver).