During August 2012, I was a visiting Scientific Researcher at the Fields Institute at the University of Toronto, participating in their thematic program on Forcing and it Applications.
Structural connections between a forcing class and its modal logic
[bibtex key=HamkinsLeibmanLoewe2015:StructuralConnectionsForcingClassAndItsModalLogic]
The modal logic of forcing arises when one considers a model of set theory in the context of all its forcing extensions, interpreting
Every definable forcing class similarly gives rise to the corresponding forcing modalities, for which one considers extensions only by forcing notions in that class. In previous work, we proved that if ZFC is consistent, then the ZFC-provably valid principles of the class of all forcing are precisely the assertions of the modal theory S4.2 (see The modal logic of forcing). In this article, we prove that the provably valid principles of collapse forcing, Cohen forcing and other classes are in each case exactly S4.3; the provably valid principles of c.c.c. forcing, proper forcing, and others are each contained within S4.3 and do not contain S4.2; the provably valid principles of countably closed forcing, CH-preserving forcing and others are each exactly S4.2; and the provably valid principles of
Preprints available at: ar
Every countable model of set theory embeds into its own constructible universe
[bibtex key=Hamkins2013:EveryCountableModelOfSetTheoryEmbedsIntoItsOwnL]
In this article, I prove that every countable model of set theory
that is elementary for quantifier-free assertions in the language of set theory.
Main Theorem 1. Every countable model of set theory
The proof uses universal digraph combinatorics, including an acyclic version of the countable random digraph, which I call the countable random
Main Theorem 2. The countable models of set theory are linearly pre-ordered by embeddability: for any two countable models of set theory
The proof shows that the embeddability relation on the models of set theory conforms with their ordinal heights, in that any two models with the same ordinals are bi-embeddable; any shorter model embeds into any taller model; and the ill-founded models are all bi-embeddable and universal.
The proof method arises most easily in finite set theory, showing that the nonstandard hereditarily finite sets
Main Theorem 3. If
In particular, every countable model of ZFC and even of ZFC plus large cardinals arises as a submodel of
The proof, in brief: for every countable acyclic digraph, consider the partial order induced by the edge relation, and extend this order to a total order, which may be embedded in the rational order
The article closes with a number of questions, which I record here (and which I have also asked on mathoverflow: Can there be an embedding
Question 1. Can there be an embedding
By embedding, I mean an isomorphism from
It they are not outright refutable, then it would seem natural that these questions might involve large cardinals; perhaps
Question 2. Does every set
The main theorem shows that every countable set
Question 3. Does
It is also natural to inquire about the nature of
Question 4. Does every countable model
Probably one can arrange this simply by being a bit more careful with the modified Mostowski procedure in the proof of the main theorem. And if this is correct, then numerous further questions immediately come to mind, concerning the extent to which we ensure more attractive features for the embeddings
Question 5. Can there be a nontrivial embedding
Finally, I inquire about the extent to which the main theorems of the article can be extended from the countable models of set theory to the
Question 6. Does every
Well-founded Boolean ultrapowers as large cardinal embeddings
[bibtex key=HamkinsSeabold:BooleanUltrapowers]
Boolean ultrapowers extend the classical ultrapower construction to work with ultrafilters on any complete Boolean algebra, rather than only on a power set algebra. When they are well-founded, the associated Boolean ultrapower embeddings exhibit a large cardinal nature, and the Boolean ultrapower construction thereby unifies two central themes of set theoryβforcing and large cardinalsβby revealing them to be two facets of a single underlying construction, the Boolean ultrapower.
The topic of this article was the focus of my tutorial lecture series at the Young Set Theorists Workshop at the Hausdorff Center for Mathematics in KΓΆnigswinter near Bonn, Germany, March 21-25, 2011.
Singular cardinals and strong extenders
[bibtex key=ApterCummingsHamkins2013:SingularCardinalsAndStrongExtenders]
Brent Cody asked the question whether the situation can arise that one has an elementary embedding
In this article, we investigate the various circumstances in which this does and does not happen, the circumstances under which there exist a singular cardinal
The mate-in-n problem of infinite chess is decidable, Cambridge, June 2012
This will be a contributed talk at the Turing Centenary Conference CiE 2012 held June 18-23, 2012 in Cambridge, UK.
Abstract. The mate-in-
The hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility, Chicheley Hall, June 2012
This will be a talk at The Incomputable, a workshop held June 12-15, 2012 at the Kavli Royal Society International Centre at Chicheley Hall as a part of the program Semantics and Syntax: A Legacy of Alan Turing organized by the Isaac Newton Institute of Mathematical Sciences in Cambridge, UK.
Abstract. I will speak on the computable analogue of the theory of equivalence relations on the reals under Borel reducibility. The Borel theory has been enormously successful in clarifying the hierarchy of classification problems arising throughout mathematics. The computable analogue, meanwhile, appears to be particularly well-suited for an analysis of the c.e. instances of those problems, a rich context with many natural examples, such as the isomorphism relation on c.e. graphs or on computably presented groups. In particular, every equivalence relation on countable structures has its natural restriction to the c.e. instances, which may be viewed as an equivalence relation on the indices of those c.e. sets. Specifically, one equivalence relation E on the natural numbers is computably reducible to another F, if there is a computable function f such that n E m if and only if f(n) F f(m). This reduction notion has been introduced and studied independently by several different researchers and research groups. In this talk, I will describe recent joint work with Sam Coskey and Russell Miller that fills out parts of the hierarchy. An abundance of questions remain open.
The countable models of ZFC, up to isomorphism, are linearly pre-ordered by the submodel relation; indeed, every countable model of ZFC, including every transitive model, is isomorphic to a submodel of its own πΏ , New York, 2012
This will be a talk on May 18, 2012 for the CUNY Logic Workshop on some extremely new work. The proof uses finitary digraph combinatorics, including the countable random digraph and higher analogues involving uncountable Fraisse limits, the surreal numbers and the hypnagogic digraph.
The story begins with Ressayreβs remarkable 1983 result that if
My new theorem strengthens Ressayreβs theorem, while simplifying the proof, by removing the theory
Theorem.(JDH) Every countable model of set theory is isomorphic to a submodel of any nonstandard model of finite set theory. Indeed, every nonstandard model of finite set theory is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations.
The proof involves the construction of what I call the countable random
The proof, in brief: for every countable acyclic digraph, consider the partial order induced by the edge relation, and extend this order to a total order, which may be embedded in the rational order
The proof idea adapts, with complications, to the case of well-founded models, via the countable random
Theorem.(JDH) Every countable model
The proof is guided by the idea of finding a universal submodel inside
Corollary.(JDH) The countable models of ZFC are linearly ordered and even well-ordered, up to isomorphism, by the submodel relation. Namely, any two countable models of ZFC with the same well-founded height are bi-embeddable as submodels of each other, and all models embed into any nonstandard model.
The work opens up numerous questions on the extent to which we may expect in ZFC that
The omega one of infinite chess, New York, 2012
This will be a talk on May 18, 2012 for the CUNY Set Theory Seminar.
Infinite chess is chess played on an infinite edgeless chessboard. The familiar chess pieces move about according to their usual chess rules, and each player strives to place the opposing king into checkmate. The mate-in-
article | slides
Must there be numbers we cannot describe or define? Pointwise definability and the Math Tea argument, Bristol, April 2012
This is a talk I plan to give to the set theory seminar at the University of Bristol on April 18, 2012.
An old argument, heard at a good math tea, proceeds: βthere must be some real numbers that we can neither describe nor define, since there are uncountably many reals, but only countably many definitions.β Does it withstand scrutiny? In this talk, I will discuss the phenomenon of pointwise definable models of set theory, in which every object is definable without parameters. In addition to classical and folklore results on the existence of pointwise definable models of set theory, the main new theorem is that every countable model of ZFC and indeed of GBC has an extension to a model of set theory with the same ordinals, in which every set and class is definable without parameters. This is joint work with Jonas Reitz and David Linetsky, and builds on work of S. Simpson, R. Kossak, J. Schmerl, S. Friedman and A. Enayat.
A course in infinitary computability, Fall 2012, CUNY Graduate Center, CSC 85020
In Fall 2012 I will teach a graduate course on infinitary computability theory in the Computer Science program at the CUNY Graduate Center. This course will be aimed at graduate students in computer science and mathematics who are interested in infinitary computational processes.
Infinitary computability, CSC 85020, Mondays, 9:30 β 11:30 am
CS course listings | this listing
This course will explore all the various infinitary theories of computability, including infinite time Turing machines, Blum-Shub-Smale computability, BΓΌchi automata, ordinal register machines and others. The focus will be on introducing the computability models and comparing them to each other and to standard concepts of computability. In the early part of the course, we shall review the standard finitary computational models, before investigating the infinitary supertask analogues.
Students wishing to prepare for the course should review their understanding of Turing machines and the other theoretical machine models of computation.
Some of my articles on infinitary computability | Student talks on their infinitary computability term papers
Fun and paradox with large numbers, logic and infinity, Philadelphia 2012
This is a fun talk I will give at Temple University for the mathematics undergraduates in the Senior Problem Solving forum. Weβll be exploring some of the best puzzles and paradoxes I know of that arise with large numbers and infinity. Many of these paradoxes are connected with deep issues surrounding the nature of mathematical truth, and my intention is to convey some of that depth, while still being accessible and entertaining.
Abstract: Are there some real numbers that in principle cannot be described? What is the largest natural number that can be written or described in ordinary type on a 3Γ5 index card? Which is bigger, a googol-bang-plex or a googol-plex-bang? Is every natural number interesting? Is every true statement provable? Does every mathematical problem ultimately reduce to a computational procedure? Is every sentence either true or false or neither true nor false? Can one complete a task involving infinitely many steps? We will explore these and many other puzzles and paradoxes involving large numbers, logic and infinity, and along the way, learn some interesting mathematics.
What happens when one iteratively computes the automorphism group of a group? Temple University, Philadelphia 2012
This is a talk I shall give for the Mathematics Colloquium at Temple University, April 23, 2012.
The automorphism tower of a group is obtained by computing its automorphism group, the automorphism group of that group, and so on, iterating transfinitely. The question, known as the automorphism tower problem, is whether the tower ever terminates, whether there is eventually a fixed point, a group that is isomorphic to its automorphism group by the natural map. Wielandt (1939) proved the classical result that the automorphism tower of any finite centerless group terminates in finitely many steps. This was successively generalized to larger and larger collections of groups until Thomas (1985) proved that every centerless group has a terminating automorphism tower. Building on this, I proved (1997) that every group has a terminating automorphism tower. After giving an account of this theorem, I will give an overview of work with Simon Thomas and newer work with Gunter Fuchs and work of Philipp LΓΌcke, which reveal a set-theoretic essence for the automorphism tower of a group: the very same group can have wildly different towers in different models of set theory.
slides | list of my articles on automorphism towers | announcement poster
The automorphism tower problem for groups, Bristol 2012
Isaac Newton 20th Anniversary Lecture. This is a talk I shall give at the University of Bristol, School of Mathematics, April 17, 2012, at the invitation of Philip Welch.
The automorphism tower of a group is obtained by computing its automorphism group, the automorphism group of that group, and so on, iterating transfinitely. The question, known as the automorphism tower problem, is whether the tower ever terminates, whether there is eventually a fixed point, a group that is isomorphic to its automorphism group by the natural map. Wielandt (1939) proved the classical result that the automorphism tower of any finite centerless group terminates in finitely many steps. This was successively generalized to larger and larger collections of groups until Thomas (1985) proved that every centerless group has a terminating automorphism tower. Building on this, I proved (1997) that every group has a terminating automorphism tower. After giving an account of this theorem, I will give an overview of my work with Simon Thomas, as well as newer work with Gunter Fuchs and work of Philipp LΓΌcke, which reveal a set-theoretic essence for the automorphism tower of a group: the very same group can have wildly different towers in different models of set theory.
slides | list of my articles on automorphism towers | abstract at Bristol
The hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility, Cambridge, March 2012
This is a talk I shall give at the workshop on Logical Approaches to Barriers in Complexity II, March 26-30, 2012, a part of the program Semantics and Syntax: A Legacy of Alan Turing at the Isaac Newton Institute for Mathematical Sciences in Cambridge, where I am currently a Visiting Fellow.
Many of the naturally arising equivalence relations in mathematics, such as isomorphism relations on various types of countable structures, turn out to be equivalence relations on a standard Borel space, and these relations form an intensely studied hierarchy under Borel reducibility. The topic of this talk is to introduce and explore the computable analogue of this robust theory, by studying the corresponding hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility. Specifically, one relation
Slides | Slides (longer version, from a similar talk) | Article | Conference abstract | Video