Fields Institute, Toronto, Scientific Researcher, 2012

During August 2012, I was a visiting Scientific Researcher at the Fields Institute at the University of Toronto, participating in their thematic program on Forcing and it Applications.

Structural connections between a forcing class and its modal logic

[bibtex key=HamkinsLeibmanLoewe2015:StructuralConnectionsForcingClassAndItsModalLogic]

The modal logic of forcing arises when one considers a model of set theory in the context of all its forcing extensions, interpreting β—» as β€œin all forcing extensions” and β—Š as β€œin some forcing extension”. In this modal language one may easily express sweeping general forcing principles, such as β—Šβ—»πœ‘ β†’β—»β—Šπœ‘, the assertion that every possibly necessary statement is necessarily possible, which is valid for forcing, or β—Šβ—»πœ‘ β†’πœ‘, the assertion that every possibly necessary statement is true, which is the maximality principle, a forcing axiom independent of but equiconsistent with ZFC (see A simple maximality principle).

Every definable forcing class similarly gives rise to the corresponding forcing modalities, for which one considers extensions only by forcing notions in that class. In previous work, we proved that if ZFC is consistent, then the ZFC-provably valid principles of the class of all forcing are precisely the assertions of the modal theory S4.2 (see The modal logic of forcing). In this article, we prove that the provably valid principles of collapse forcing, Cohen forcing and other classes are in each case exactly S4.3; the provably valid principles of c.c.c. forcing, proper forcing, and others are each contained within S4.3 and do not contain S4.2; the provably valid principles of countably closed forcing, CH-preserving forcing and others are each exactly S4.2; and the provably valid principles of πœ”1-preserving forcing are contained within S4.tBA. All these results arise from general structural connections we have identified between a forcing class and the modal logic of forcing to which it gives rise, including the connection between various control statements, such as buttons, switches and ratchets, and their corresponding forcing validities. These structural connections therefore support a forcing-only analysis of other diverse forcing classes.

Preprints available at:  arπœ’iv | NI12055-SAS | UvA ILLC PP-2012-19 | HBM 446

Every countable model of set theory embeds into its own constructible universe

[bibtex key=Hamkins2013:EveryCountableModelOfSetTheoryEmbedsIntoItsOwnL]

In this article, I prove that every countable model of set theory βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©, including every well-founded model, is isomorphic to a submodel of its own constructible universe βŸ¨πΏπ‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©. Another way to say this is that there is an embedding
𝑗:βŸ¨π‘€,βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©β†’βŸ¨πΏπ‘€,βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©
that is elementary for quantifier-free assertions in the language of set theory.

Main Theorem 1. Every countable model of set theory βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© is isomorphic to a submodel of its own constructible universe βŸ¨πΏπ‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©.

The proof uses universal digraph combinatorics, including an acyclic version of the countable random digraph, which I call the countable random β„š-graded digraph, and higher analogues arising as uncountable Fraisse limits, leading eventually to what I call the hypnagogic digraph, a set-homogeneous, class-universal, surreal-numbers-graded acyclic class digraph, which is closely connected with the surreal numbers. The proof shows that βŸ¨πΏπ‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© contains a submodel that is a universal acyclic digraph of rank Ord𝑀, and so in fact this model is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations of this rank. When 𝑀 is ill-founded, this includes all acyclic binary relations. The method of proof also establishes the following, thereby answering a question posed by Ewan Delanoy.

Main Theorem 2. The countable models of set theory are linearly pre-ordered by embeddability: for any two countable models of set theory βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© and βŸ¨π‘, βˆˆπ‘βŸ©, either 𝑀 is isomorphic to a submodel of 𝑁 or conversely. Indeed, the countable models of set theory are pre-well-ordered by embeddability in order type exactly πœ”1 +1.

The proof shows that the embeddability relation on the models of set theory conforms with their ordinal heights, in that any two models with the same ordinals are bi-embeddable; any shorter model embeds into any taller model; and the ill-founded models are all bi-embeddable and universal.

The proof method arises most easily in finite set theory, showing that the nonstandard hereditarily finite sets HF𝑀 coded in any nonstandard model 𝑀 of PA or even of 𝐼⁒Δ0 are similarly universal for all acyclic binary relations. This strengthens a classical theorem of Ressayre, while simplifying the proof, replacing a partial saturation and resplendency argument with a soft appeal to graph universality.

Main Theorem 3. If 𝑀 is any nonstandard model of PA, then every countable model of set theory is isomorphic to a submodel of the hereditarily finite sets ⟨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© of 𝑀. Indeed, ⟨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations.

In particular, every countable model of ZFC and even of ZFC plus large cardinals arises as a submodel of ⟨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©. Thus, inside any nonstandard model of finite set theory, we may cast out some of the finite sets and thereby arrive at a copy of any desired model of infinite set theory, having infinite sets, uncountable sets or even large cardinals of whatever type we like.

The proof, in brief:  for every countable acyclic digraph, consider the partial order induced by the edge relation, and extend this order to a total order, which may be embedded in the rational order β„š.  Thus, every countable acyclic digraph admits a β„š-grading, an assignmment of rational numbers to nodes such that all edges point upwards. Next, one can build a countable homogeneous, universal, existentially closed β„š-graded digraph, simply by starting with nothing, and then adding finitely many nodes at each stage, so as to realize the finite pattern property. The result is a computable presentation of what I call the countable random β„š-graded digraph Ξ“.  If 𝑀 is any nonstandard model of finite set theory, then we may run this computable construction inside 𝑀 for a nonstandard number of steps.  The standard part of this nonstandard finite graph includes a copy of Ξ“.  Furthermore, since 𝑀 thinks it is finite and acyclic, it can perform a modified Mostowski collapse to realize the graph in the hereditary finite sets of 𝑀.  By looking at the sets corresponding to the nodes in the copy of Ξ“, we find a submodel of 𝑀 that is isomorphic to Ξ“, which is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations. So every model of ZFC isomorphic to a submodel of 𝑀.

The article closes with a number of questions, which I record here (and which I have also asked on mathoverflow:  Can there be an embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 from the set-theoretic universe 𝑉 to the constructible universe 𝐿, when 𝑉 ≠𝐿?) Although the main theorem shows that every countable model of set theory embeds into its own constructible universe  π‘—:𝑀→𝐿𝑀, this embedding 𝑗 is constructed completely externally to 𝑀 and there is little reason to expect that 𝑗 could be a class in 𝑀 or otherwise amenable to 𝑀.  To what extent can we prove or refute the possibility that 𝑗 is a class in 𝑀? This amounts to considering the matter internally as a question about 𝑉. Surely it would seem strange to have a class embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 when 𝑉 ≠𝐿, even if it is elementary only for quantifier-free assertions, since such an embedding is totally unlike the sorts of embeddings that one usually encounters in set theory. Nevertheless, I am at a loss to refute the hypothesis, and the possibility that there might be such an embedding is intriguing, if not tantalizing, for one imagines all kinds of constructions that pull structure from 𝐿 back into 𝑉.

Question 1.  Can there be an embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 when 𝑉 ≠𝐿?

By embedding, I mean an isomorphism from βŸ¨π‘‰, ∈⟩ to its range in ⟨𝐿, ∈⟩, which is the same as a quantifier-free-elementary map 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿. The question is most naturally formalized in GΓΆdel-Bernays set theory, asking whether there can be a GB-class 𝑗 forming such an embedding.  If one wants 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 to be a definable class, then this of course implies 𝑉 =HOD, since the definable 𝐿-order can be pulled back to 𝑉, via π‘₯ ≀𝑦 ⟺ 𝑗⁑(𝑠) ≀𝐿𝑗⁑(𝑦). More generally, if 𝑗 is merely a class in GΓΆdel-Bernays set theory, then the existence of an embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 implies global choice, since from the class 𝑗 we can pull back the 𝐿-order. For these reasons, we cannot expect every model of ZFC or of GB to have such embeddings. Can they be added generically? Do they have some large cardinal strength? Are they outright refutable?

It they are not outright refutable, then it would seem natural that these questions might involve large cardinals; perhaps 0β™― is relevant. But I am unsure which way the answers will go. The existence of large cardinals provides extra strength, but may at the same time make it harder to have the embedding, since it pushes 𝑉 further away from 𝐿. For example, it is conceivable that the existence of 0β™― will enable one to construct the embedding, using the Silver indiscernibles to find a universal submodel of 𝐿; but it is also conceivable that the non-existence of 0β™―, because of covering and the corresponding essential closeness of 𝑉 to 𝐿, may make it easier for such a 𝑗 to exist. Or perhaps it is simply refutable in any case. The first-order analogue of the question is:

Question 2.  Does every set 𝐴 admit an embedding 𝑗 :⟨𝐴, ∈⟩ β†’βŸ¨πΏ, ∈⟩?  If not, which sets do admit such embeddings?

The main theorem shows that every countable set 𝐴 embeds into 𝐿. What about uncountable sets? Let us make the question extremely concrete:

Question 3. Does βŸ¨π‘‰πœ”+1, ∈⟩ embed into ⟨𝐿, ∈⟩? How about βŸ¨π‘ƒβ‘(πœ”), ∈⟩ or ⟨HC, ∈⟩?

It is also natural to inquire about the nature of 𝑗 :𝑀 →𝐿𝑀 even when it is not a class in 𝑀. For example, can one find such an embedding for which 𝑗⁑(𝛼) is an ordinal whenever 𝛼 is an ordinal?  The embedding arising in the proof of the main theorem definitely does not have this feature.

Question 4. Does every countable model βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© of set theory admit an embedding 𝑗 :𝑀 →𝐿𝑀 that takes ordinals to ordinals?

Probably one can arrange this simply by being a bit more careful with the modified Mostowski procedure in the proof of the main theorem.  And if this is correct, then numerous further questions immediately come to mind, concerning the extent to which we ensure more attractive features for the embeddings 𝑗 that arise in the main theorems. This will be particularly interesting in the case of well-founded models, as well as in the case of 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿, as in question , if that should be possible.

Question 5. Can there be a nontrivial embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿 that takes ordinals to ordinals?

Finally, I inquire about the extent to which the main theorems of the article can be extended from the countable models of set theory to the πœ”1-like models:

Question 6. Does every πœ”1-like model of set theory βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© admit an embedding 𝑗 :𝑀 →𝐿𝑀 into its own constructible universe? Are the πœ”1-like models of set theory linearly pre-ordered by embeddability?

Singular cardinals and strong extenders

[bibtex key=ApterCummingsHamkins2013:SingularCardinalsAndStrongExtenders]

Brent Cody asked the question whether the situation can arise that one has an elementary embedding 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝑀 witnessing the πœƒ-strongness of a cardinal πœ…, but where πœƒ is regular in 𝑀 and singular in 𝑉.

In this article, we investigate the various circumstances in which this does and does not happen, the circumstances under which there exist a singular cardinal πœ‡ and a short (πœ…,πœ‡)-extender 𝐸 witnessing β€œπœ… is πœ‡-strong”, such that πœ‡ is singular in π‘ˆβ’π‘™β’π‘‘β‘(𝑉,𝐸).

The mate-in-n problem of infinite chess is decidable, Cambridge, June 2012

This will be a contributed talk at the Turing Centenary Conference CiE 2012 held June 18-23, 2012 in Cambridge, UK.

Abstract.  The mate-in-𝑛 problem of infinite chessβ€”chess played on an infinite edgeless boardβ€”is the problem of determining whether a designated player can force a win from a given finite position in at most 𝑛 moves. Although a straightforward formulation of this problem leads to assertions of high arithmetic complexity, with 2⁒𝑛 alternating quantifiers,  the main theorem of this article nevertheless confirms a conjecture of the second author and C. D. A. Evans by establishing that it is computably decidable, uniformly in the position and in 𝑛. Furthermore, there is a computable strategy for optimal play from such mate-in-𝑛 positions. The proof proceeds by showing that the mate-in-𝑛 problem is expressible in what we call the first-order structure of chess β„­π”₯, which we prove (in the relevant fragment) is an automatic structure, whose theory is therefore decidable. The structure is also definable in Presburger arithmetic. Unfortunately, this resolution of the mate-in-𝑛 problem does not appear to settle the decidability of the more general winning-position problem, the problem of determining whether a designated player has a winning strategy from a given position, since a position may admit a winning strategy without any bound on the number of moves required. This issue is connected with transfinite game values in infinite chess, and the exact value of the omega one of chess πœ”c⁒h⁑e⁒s⁒s1 is not known.

Article | Slides | CiE 2012 | Contributed talk schedule

The hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility, Chicheley Hall, June 2012

 

This will be a talk at The Incomputable, a workshop held June 12-15, 2012 at the Kavli Royal Society International Centre at Chicheley Hall as a part of the program Semantics and Syntax: A Legacy of Alan Turing organized by the Isaac Newton Institute of Mathematical Sciences in Cambridge, UK.

Abstract.  I will speak on the computable analogue of the theory of equivalence relations on the reals under Borel reducibility.  The Borel theory has been enormously successful in clarifying the hierarchy of classification problems arising throughout mathematics.  The computable analogue, meanwhile, appears to be particularly well-suited for an analysis of the c.e. instances of those problems, a rich context with many natural examples, such as the isomorphism relation on c.e. graphs or on computably presented groups.  In particular, every equivalence relation on countable structures has its natural restriction to the c.e. instances, which may be viewed as an equivalence relation on the indices of those c.e. sets.  Specifically, one equivalence relation E on the natural numbers is computably reducible to another F, if there is a computable function f such that n E m if and only if f(n) F f(m).   This reduction notion has beenMathematical discussions with Philip Welch introduced and studied independently by several different researchers and research groups.  In this talk, I will describe recent joint work with Sam Coskey and Russell Miller that fills out parts of the hierarchy.  An abundance of questions remain open.

Article | Slides | Workshop abstract 

The countable models of ZFC, up to isomorphism, are linearly pre-ordered by the submodel relation; indeed, every countable model of ZFC, including every transitive model, is isomorphic to a submodel of its own 𝐿, New York, 2012

This will be a talk on May 18, 2012 for the CUNY Logic Workshop on some extremely new work. The proof uses finitary digraph combinatorics, including the countable random digraph and higher analogues involving uncountable Fraisse limits, the surreal numbers and the hypnagogic digraph.

The story begins with Ressayre’s remarkable 1983 result that if 𝑀 is any nonstandard model of PA, with ⟨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© the corresponding nonstandard hereditary finite sets of 𝑀, then for any consistent computably axiomatized theory 𝑇 in the language of set theory, with 𝑇 βŠƒπ‘β’πΉ, there is a submodel 𝑁 βŠ‚βŸ¨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© such that 𝑁 βŠ§π‘‡. In particular, one may find models of ZFC or even ZFC + large cardinals as submodels of HF𝑀, a land where everything is thought to be finite. Incredible! Ressayre’s proof uses partial saturation and resplendency to prove that one can find the submodel of the desired theory 𝑇.

My new theorem strengthens Ressayre’s theorem, while simplifying the proof, by removing the theory 𝑇. We need not assume 𝑇 is computable, and we don’t just get one model of 𝑇, but rather all modelsβ€”the fact is that the nonstandard models of set theory are universal for all countable acyclic binary relations. So every model of set theory is a submodel of ⟨HF𝑀, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©.

Theorem.(JDH) Every countable model of set theory is isomorphic to a submodel of any nonstandard model of finite set theory. Indeed, every nonstandard model of finite set theory is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations.

The proof involves the construction of what I call the countable random β„š-graded digraph, a countable homogeneous acyclic digraph that is universal for all countable acyclic digraphs, and proving that it is realized as a submodel of the nonstandard model βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©. Having then realized a universal object as a submodel, it follows that every countable structure with an acyclic binary relation, including every countable model of ZFC, is realized as a submodel of 𝑀.

The proof, in brief:  for every countable acyclic digraph, consider the partial order induced by the edge relation, and extend this order to a total order, which may be embedded in the rational order β„š.  Thus, every countable acyclic digraph admits a β„š-grading, an assignmment of rational numbers to nodes such that all edges point upwards. Next, one can build a countable homogeneous, universal, existentially closed β„š-graded digraph, simply by starting with nothing, and then adding finitely many nodes at each stage, so as to realize the finite pattern property. The result is a computable presentation of what I call the countable random β„š-graded digraph Ξ“.  If 𝑀 is any nonstandard model of finite set theory, then we may run this computable construction inside 𝑀 for a nonstandard number of steps.  The standard part of this nonstandard finite graph includes a copy of Ξ“.  Furthermore, since 𝑀 thinks it is finite and acyclic, it can perform a modified Mostowski collapse to realize the graph in the hereditary finite sets of 𝑀.  By looking at the sets corresponding to the nodes in the copy of Ξ“, we find a submodel of 𝑀 that is isomorphic to Ξ“, which is universal for all countable acyclic binary relations. So every model of ZFC isomorphic to a submodel of 𝑀.

The proof idea adapts, with complications, to the case of well-founded models, via the countable random πœ†-graded digraph, as well as the internal construction of what I call the hypnagogic digraph, a proper class homogeneous surreal-numbers-graded digraph, which is universal for all class acyclic digraphs.

Theorem.(JDH) Every countable model βŸ¨π‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ© of ZFC, including the transitive models, is isomorphic to a submodel of its own constructible universe βŸ¨πΏπ‘€, βˆˆπ‘€βŸ©. In other words, there is an embedding 𝑗 :𝑀 →𝐿𝑀 that is quantifier-free-elementary.

The proof is guided by the idea of finding a universal submodel inside 𝐿𝑀. The embedding 𝑗 is constructed completely externally to 𝑀.

Corollary.(JDH) The countable models of ZFC are linearly ordered and even well-ordered, up to isomorphism, by the submodel relation. Namely, any two countable models of ZFC with the same well-founded height are bi-embeddable as submodels of each other, and all models embed into any nonstandard model.

The work opens up numerous questions on the extent to which we may expect in ZFC that 𝑉 might be isomorphic to a subclass of 𝐿. To what extent can we expect to have or to refute embeddings 𝑗 :𝑉 →𝐿, elementary for quantifier-free assertions?

Article | CUNY Logic Workshop

The omega one of infinite chess, New York, 2012

This will be a talk on May 18, 2012 for the CUNY Set Theory Seminar.

Infinite chess is chess played on an infinite edgeless chessboard. The familiar chess pieces move about according to their usual chess rules, and each player strives to place the opposing king into checkmate.  The mate-in-𝑛 problem of infinite chess is the problem of determining whether a designated player can force a win from a given finite position in at most 𝑛 moves.  A naive formulation of this problem leads to assertions of high arithmetic complexity with 2⁒𝑛 alternating quantifiersβ€”there is a move for white, such that for every black reply, there is a countermove for white, and so on. In such a formulation, the problem does not appear to be decidable; and one cannot expect to search an infinitely branching game tree even to finite depth. Nevertheless, in joint work with Dan Brumleve and Philipp Schlicht, confirming a conjecture of myself and C. D. A. Evans, we establish that the mate-in-𝑛 problem of infinite chess is computably decidable, uniformly in the position and in 𝑛. Furthermore, there is a computable strategy for optimal play from such mate-in-𝑛 positions. The proof proceeds by showing that the mate-in-𝑛 problem is expressible in what we call the first-order structure of chess, which we prove (in the relevant fragment) is an automatic structure, whose theory is therefore decidable.  An equivalent account of the result arises from the realization that the structure of chess is interpretable in the standard model of Presburger arithmetic βŸ¨β„•, +⟩.  Unfortunately, this resolution of the mate-in-𝑛 problem does not appear to settle the decidability of the more general winning-position problem, the problem of determining whether a designated player has a winning strategy from a given position, since a position may admit a winning strategy without any bound on the number of moves required. This issue is connected with transfinite game values in infinite chess, and the exact value of the omega one of chess πœ”c⁒h⁑e⁒s⁒s1 is not known. I will also discuss recent joint work with C. D. A. Evans and W. Hugh Woodin showing that the omega one of infinite positions in three-dimensional infinite chess is true πœ”1: every countable ordinal is realized as the game value of such a position.

article | slides

Must there be numbers we cannot describe or define? Pointwise definability and the Math Tea argument, Bristol, April 2012

This is a talk I plan to give to the set theory seminar at the University of Bristol on April 18, 2012.

An old argument, heard at a good math tea, proceeds: β€œthere must be some real numbers that we can neither describe nor define, since there are uncountably many reals, but only countably many definitions.” Does it withstand scrutiny? In this talk, I will discuss the phenomenon of pointwise definable models of set theory, in which every object is definable without parameters. In addition to classical and folklore results on the existence of pointwise definable models of set theory, the main new theorem is that every countable model of ZFC and indeed of GBC has an extension to a model of set theory with the same ordinals, in which every set and class is definable without parameters. This is joint work with Jonas Reitz and David Linetsky, and builds on work of S. Simpson, R. Kossak, J. Schmerl, S. Friedman and A. Enayat.

slides | article

A course in infinitary computability, Fall 2012, CUNY Graduate Center, CSC 85020

In Fall 2012 I will teach a graduate course on infinitary computability theory in the Computer Science program at the CUNY Graduate Center.   This course will be aimed at graduate students in computer science and mathematics who are interested in infinitary computational processes.

Infinitary computability, CSC 85020, Mondays, 9:30 – 11:30 am
CS course listings | this listing

This course will explore all the various infinitary theories of computability, including infinite time Turing machines, Blum-Shub-Smale computability, BΓΌchi automata, ordinal register machines and others. The focus will be on introducing the computability models and comparing them to each other and to standard concepts of computability. In the early part of the course, we shall review the standard finitary computational models, before investigating the infinitary supertask analogues.

Students wishing to prepare for the course should review their understanding of Turing machines and the other theoretical machine models of computation.

Some of my articles on infinitary computability | Student talks on their infinitary computability term papers

Fun and paradox with large numbers, logic and infinity, Philadelphia 2012

This is a fun talk I will give at Temple University for the mathematics undergraduates in the Senior Problem Solving forum.  We’ll be exploring some of the best puzzles and paradoxes I know of that arise with large numbers and infinity.  Many of these paradoxes are connected with deep issues surrounding the nature of mathematical truth, and my intention is to convey some of that depth, while still being accessible and entertaining.

Abstract:  Are there some real numbers that in principle cannot be described?  What is the largest natural number that can be written or described  in ordinary type on a 3Γ—5 index card?  Which is bigger, a googol-bang-plex or a googol-plex-bang? Is every natural number interesting?  Is every true statement provable? Does every mathematical problem ultimately reduce to a computational procedure?  Is every sentence either true or false or neither true nor false?  Can one complete a task involving infinitely many steps?  We will explore these and many other puzzles and paradoxes involving large numbers, logic and infinity, and along the way, learn some interesting mathematics.

What happens when one iteratively computes the automorphism group of a group? Temple University, Philadelphia 2012

This is a talk I shall give for the Mathematics Colloquium at Temple University, April 23, 2012.

The automorphism tower of a group is obtained by computing its automorphism group, the automorphism group of that group, and so on, iterating transfinitely. The question, known as the automorphism tower problem, is whether the tower ever terminates, whether there is eventually a fixed point, a group that is isomorphic to its automorphism group by the natural map. Wielandt (1939) proved the classical result that the automorphism tower of any finite centerless group terminates in finitely many steps. This was successively generalized to larger and larger collections of groups until Thomas (1985) proved that every centerless group has a terminating automorphism tower.  Building on this, I proved (1997) that every group has a terminating automorphism tower.  After giving an account of this theorem, I will give an overview of work with Simon Thomas and newer work with Gunter Fuchs and work of Philipp LΓΌcke, which reveal a set-theoretic essence for the automorphism tower of a group: the very same group can have wildly different towers in different models of set theory.

slides | list of my articles on automorphism towers | announcement poster

The automorphism tower problem for groups, Bristol 2012

Isaac Newton 20th Anniversary Lecture.  This is a talk I shall give at the University of Bristol, School of Mathematics, April 17, 2012, at the invitation of Philip Welch.

The automorphism tower of a group is obtained by computing its automorphism group, the automorphism group of that group, and so on, iterating transfinitely. The question, known as the automorphism tower problem, is whether the tower ever terminates, whether there is eventually a fixed point, a group that is isomorphic to its automorphism group by the natural map. Wielandt (1939) proved the classical result that the automorphism tower of any finite centerless group terminates in finitely many steps. This was successively generalized to larger and larger collections of groups until Thomas (1985) proved that every centerless group has a terminating automorphism tower.  Building on this, I proved (1997) that every group has a terminating automorphism tower.  After giving an account of this theorem, I will give an overview of my work with Simon Thomas, as well as newer work with Gunter Fuchs and work of Philipp LΓΌcke, which reveal a set-theoretic essence for the automorphism tower of a group: the very same group can have wildly different towers in different models of set theory.

slides | list of my articles on automorphism towers | abstract at Bristol

The hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility, Cambridge, March 2012

This is a talk I shall give at the workshop on Logical Approaches to Barriers in Complexity II, March 26-30, 2012, a part of the program Semantics and Syntax: A Legacy of Alan Turing at the Isaac Newton Institute for Mathematical Sciences in Cambridge, where I am currently a Visiting Fellow.

Many of the naturally arising equivalence relations in mathematics, such as isomorphism relations on various types of countable structures, turn out to be equivalence relations on a standard Borel space, and these relations form an intensely studied hierarchy under Borel reducibility.  The topic of this talk is to introduce and explore the computable analogue of this robust theory, by studying the corresponding hierarchy of equivalence relations on the natural numbers under computable reducibility.  Specifically, one relation 𝐸 is computably reducible to another 𝐹 , if there is a unary computable function 𝑓 such that π‘₯⁒𝐸⁒𝑦 if and only if 𝑓⁑(π‘₯)⁒𝐹⁑𝑓⁑(𝑦).  This gives rise to a very different hierarchy than the Turing degrees on such relations, since it is connected with the difficulty of the corresponding classification problems, rather than with the difficulty of computing the relations themselves.  The theory is well suited for an analysis of equivalence relations on classes of c.e.  structures, a rich context with many natural examples, such as the isomorphism relation on c.e. graphs or on computably presented groups.  An abundance of open questions remain, and the subject is an attractive mix of methods from mathematical logic, computability, set theory, particularly descriptive set theory, and the rest of mathematics, subjects in which many of the equivalence relations arise.  This is joint work with Sam Coskey and Russell Miller.

Slides | Slides (longer version, from a similar talk) | Article | Conference abstract | Video